Why is falsification important to popper
The verdict is accordingly represented as a true statement of fact, but, as miscarriages of justice demonstrate all too clearly,. This … is acknowledged in the rule allowing a verdict to be quashed or revised.
This is comparable, he argues, to the case of basic statements: their acceptance-as-true is also by agreement and, as such, it also constitutes an application of a theoretical system, and. However, the agreed acceptance of basic statements, like that of judicial verdicts, remain perennially susceptible to the requirement for further interrogation. Science does not, he maintains, rest upon any foundational bedrock. Rather, the theoretical systems of science are akin to buildings in swampy ground constructed with the support of piles:.
We simply stop when we are satisfied that the piles are firm enough to carry the structure, at least for the time being. For Popper, the growth of human knowledge proceeds from our problems and from our attempts to solve them.
These attempts involve the formulation of theories which must go beyond existing knowledge and therefore require a leap of the imagination. For this reason, he places special emphasis on the role played by the creative imagination in theory formulation.
In this deductive procedure conclusions are inferred from a tentative hypothesis and are then compared with one another and with other relevant statements to determine whether they falsify or corroborate the hypothesis. Popper eliminates the contradiction by removing the demand for empirical verification in favour of empirical falsification or corroboration. Scientific theories, for him, are not inductively inferred from experience, nor is scientific experimentation carried out with a view to verifying or finally establishing the truth of theories; rather, all knowledge is provisional, conjectural, hypothetical —the universal theories of science can never be conclusively established.
For it is only by critical thought that we can eliminate false theories and determine which of the remaining theories is the best available one, in the sense of possessing the highest level of explanatory force and predictive power. In the view of many social scientists, the more probable a theory is, the better it is, and if we have to choose between two theories which differ only in that one is probable and the other is improbable, then we should choose the former. Popper rejects this.
Science values theories with a high informative content, because they possess a high predictive power and are consequently highly testable. For that reason, the more improbable a theory is the better it is scientifically, because the probability and informative content of a theory vary inversely—the higher the informative content of a theory the lower will be its probability.
Thus, the statements which are of special interest to science are those with a high informative content and consequentially a low probability, which nevertheless come close to the truth. Informative content, which is in inverse proportion to probability, is in direct proportion to testability. As a result, the severity of the test to which a theory can be subjected, and by means of which it is falsified or corroborated, is of fundamental importance.
Popper also argues that all scientific criticism must be piecemeal, i. But that is not knowledge in the sense of being conclusively established; it may be challenged at any time, especially if it is suspected that its uncritical acceptance may be responsible for difficulties which are subsequently encountered. How then can one be certain that one is questioning the right thing? The Popperian answer is that we cannot have absolute certainty here, but repeated tests usually show where the trouble lies.
As we saw, for Popper even observation statements are corrigible and open to review, and science in his view is not a quest for certain knowledge, but an evolutionary process in which hypotheses or conjectures are imaginatively proposed and tested in order to explain facts or to solve problems. For that reason, he emphasises both the importance of questioning the background knowledge when the need arises, and the significance of the fact that observation-statements are theory-laden and corrigible.
Popper was initially uneasy with the concept of truth, and in his earliest writings he avoided asserting that a theory which is corroborated is true—for clearly if every theory is an open-ended hypothesis, then ipso facto it has to be at least potentially false.
Popper offers two accounts of how rival theories can be compared in terms of their levels of verisimilitude; these are the qualitative and quantitative definitions. On the quantitative account, verisimilitude is defined by assigning quantities to contents, where the index of the content of a given theory is its logical improbability, given again that content and probability vary inversely —4.
Thus, scientific progress involves, on this view, the abandonment of partially true, but falsified, theories, for theories with a higher level of verisimilitude, i. In this way, verisimilitude allowed Popper to mitigate what some saw as the pessimism of an anti-inductivist philosophy of science.
With the introduction of the concept, Popper was able to represent his account as an essentially realistic position in terms of which scientific progress can be seen as progress towards the truth, and experimental corroboration can be viewed as an indicator of verisimilitude.
The concept is most important in his system because of its application to theories which are approximations which are common in the social sciences and thus known to be false. In this connection, Popper had written:.
Ultimately, the idea of verisimilitude is most important in cases where we know that we have to work with theories which are at best approximations—that is to say, theories of which we know that they cannot be true… In these cases we can still speak of better or worse approximations to the truth and we therefore do not need to interpret these cases in an instrumentalist sense. In the first place, he acknowledges the deficiencies in his own formal account:.
This suggestion was to precipitate a great deal of important technical research in the field. He additionally moves the task of formally defining the concept from centre-stage in his philosophy of science by protesting that he had never intended to imply. Instead, he argues, the chief value of the concept is heuristic, in which the absence of an adequate formal definition is not an insuperable impediment to its utilisation in the actual appraisal of theories relativised to problems in which we have an interest.
Questions relating to the origins of convictions, feelings of certainty and the like, he argues, are properly considered the province of psychology; their attempted use in epistemology, which has been characteristic in particular of some schools of empiricism, can lead only to confusion and ultimately to scepticism.
Against it, he repeatedly insists on the objectivity of scientific knowledge and sees it as the principal task of epistemology to engage with the questions of justification and validity in that connection 7.
It is characteristic of evolutionary processes, he points out, that they come to take place in an environment which is itself in part fashioned by the species in question. Examples of this abound, such as the reefs built by corals, the hives built by bees, the dams built by beavers and the atmospheric effects yielded by plants. These are our myths, our ideas, our art works and our scientific theories about the world in which we live. When placed in an evolutionary context, he suggests, such products must be viewed instrumentally, as exosomatic artefacts.
Chief amongst them is knowledge. These latter activities are seen by Popper as growth-promoting in the evolution of knowledge, which he represents by means of a tetradic schema :. This kind of knowledge development, Popper argues, cannot be explained either by physicalism, which seeks to reduce all mental processes and states to material ones, or by dualism, which usually seeks to explicate knowledge by means of psychological categories such as thought, perception and belief.
That world is the world. In short, world 3 is the world of human cultural artifacts, which are products of world 2 mental processes, usually instantiated in the physical world 1 environment. Popper proceeds to explicate his distinction between the subjective and objective senses of knowledge by reference to this ontology. Knowledge in the objective sense, by contrast, consists not of thought processes but of thought contents , that is to say, the content of propositionalised theories: it is.
The objective thought content is that which remains invariant in a reasonably good translation. And it is that thought content, when linguistically codified in texts, works of art, log tables, mathematical formulae, which constitutes world 3, to which objective knowledge relates. For those who would suggest that such objects are mere abstractions from world 2 thought processes, Popper counters that world 3 objects are necessarily more than the thought processes which have led to their creation.
Moreover, what is most characteristic about such objects is that, unlike world 2 mental processes, they can stand in logical relationships to each other, such as equivalence, deducibility and compatibility, which makes them amenable to the kind of critical rational analysis and development that is one of the hallmarks of science.
As he puts it,. Criticism of world 3 objects is of the greatest importance, both in art and especially in science.
Science can be said to be largely the result of the critical examination and selection of conjectures, of thought contents. Each one of these, he contends, is a world 3 object that transcends both its physical, world 1 embodiments and its world 2 cognitive origins Popper was aware that he would be accused of hypostatising abstractions in asserting the reality and objectivity of world 3 objects.
He is therefore content, if required, to express his account of objective knowledge in more familiar and perhaps more mundane terms: world 3 objects are abstract objects while their physical embodiments are concrete objects. But that should not be allowed to disguise the fact that he saw the relationships between the three categories of his ontology as of enormous importance in understanding the role of science as an element of culture:.
He understood holism as the view that human social groupings are greater than the sum of their members, that they act on their human members and shape their destinies and that they are subject to their own independent laws of development.
The link between them is that holism holds that individuals are essentially formed by the social groupings to which they belong, while historicism suggests that we can understand such a social grouping only in terms of the internal principles which determine its development. Popper thinks that this view of the social sciences is both theoretically misconceived and socially dangerous, as it can give rise to totalitarianism and authoritarianism—to centralised governmental control of the individual and the attempted imposition of large-scale social planning.
Against this, he advances the view that any human social grouping is no more or less than the sum of its individual members, that what happens in history is the largely unforeseeable result of the actions of such individuals, and that large scale social planning to an antecedently conceived blueprint is inherently misconceived—and inevitably disastrous—precisely because human actions have consequences which cannot be foreseen.
Popper, then, is an historical indeterminist , insofar as he holds that history does not evolve in accordance with intrinsic laws or principles, that in the absence of such laws and principles unconditional prediction in the social sciences is an impossibility, and that there is no such thing as historical necessity. We make theoretical progress in science by subjecting our theories to critical scrutiny, and abandoning those which have been falsified.
So too in an open society the rights of the individual to criticise administrative policies will be safeguarded and upheld, undesirable policies will be eliminated in a manner analogous to the elimination of falsified scientific theories, and political differences will be resolved by critical discussion and argument rather than by coercion. The open society as thus conceived of by Popper may be defined as. Levinson Such as society is not a utopian ideal, Popper argues, but an empirically realised form of social organisation which is in every respect superior to its real or potential totalitarian rivals.
His strategy, however, is not merely to engage in a moral defence of the ideology of liberalism, but rather to show that totalitarianism is typically based upon historicist and holist presuppositions, and of demonstrating that these presuppositions are fundamentally incoherent. This dream was given impetus, he suggests, by the emergence of a genuine predictive capability regarding solar and lunar eclipses at an early stage in human civilisation, which became refined with the development of the natural sciences.
Why should we not conceive of a social science which would function as the theoretical natural sciences function and yield precise unconditional predictions in the appropriate sphere of application? Popper seeks to show to show that this idea is based upon a series of misconceptions about the nature of science, and about the relationship between scientific laws and scientific prediction.
Contrary to popular belief, it is the former rather than the latter which are typical of the natural sciences, which means that typically prediction in natural science is conditional and limited in scope—it takes the form of hypothetical assertions stating that certain specified changes will come about if and only if particular specified events antecedently take place.
However, Popper argues that a these unconditional prophecies are not characteristic of the natural sciences, and b that the mechanism whereby they occur, in the very limited way in which they do, is not understood by the historicist. Given that this is the mechanism which generates unconditional scientific prophecies, Popper makes two related claims about historicism:. The first is that the historicist does not, as a matter of fact, derive his historical prophecies from conditional scientific predictions.
The second … is that he cannot possibly do so because long term prophecies can be derived from scientific conditional predictions only if they apply to systems which can be described as well isolated, stationary, and recurrent.
These systems are very rare in nature; and modern society is surely not one of them. Popper accordingly argues that it is a fundamental mistake for the historicist to take the unconditional scientific prophecies of eclipses as being typical and characteristic of the predictions of natural science; they are possible only because our solar system is a stationary and repetitive system which is isolated from other such systems by immense expanses of empty space.
Human society and human history are not isolated systems and are continually undergoing rapid, non-repetitive development. In the most fundamental sense possible, every event in human history is discrete, novel, quite unique, and ontologically distinct from every other historical event.
For this reason, it is impossible in principle that unconditional scientific prophecies could be made in relation to human history—the idea that the successful unconditional prediction of eclipses provides us with reasonable grounds for the hope of successful unconditional prediction regarding the evolution of human history turns out to be based upon a gross misconception.
An additional mistake which Popper discerns in historicism is the failure of the historicist to distinguish between scientific laws and trends. This makes him think it possible to explain change by discovering trends running through past history, and to anticipate and predict future occurrences on the basis of such observations. Here Popper points out that there is a critical difference between a trend and a scientific law: the latter is universal in form, while a trend can be expressed only as a singular existential statement.
This logical difference is crucial: neither conditional nor unconditional predictions can be based upon trends, because trends may change or be reversed with a change in the conditions which gave rise to them in the first instance. As Popper puts it, there can be no doubt that. He does not, of course, dispute the existence of trends or deny that observing them can be of practical utility value. But the essential point is that a trend is something which itself ultimately stands in need of scientific explanation, and it cannot therefore function as the frame of reference in terms of which an unconditional prediction can be based.
A point which connects with this has to do with the role which the evolution of human knowledge has played in the historical development of human society. Human history has, Popper points out, been strongly influenced by the growth of human knowledge , and it is extremely likely that this will continue to be the case—all the empirical evidence suggests that the link between the two is progressively consolidating.
Quine states that a theory is not a single statement; it is a complex network a collection of statements. You might falsify one statement e. Critics of Karl Popper, chiefly Thomas Kuhn , Paul Feyerabend, and Imre Lakatos, rejected the idea that there exists a single method that applies to all science and could account for its progress. McLeod, S. Karl popper - theory of falsification. Simply Psychology. Toggle navigation.
Saul McLeod , updated Summary of Popper's Theory Karl Popper believed that scientific knowledge is provisional — the best we can do at the moment. Popper is known for his attempt to refute the classical positivist account of the scientific method, by replacing induction with the falsification principle.
The Falsification Principle, proposed by Karl Popper, is a way of demarcating science from non-science. It suggests that for a theory to be considered scientific it must be able to be tested and conceivably proven false.
For example, the hypothesis that "all swans are white," can be falsified by observing a black swan. For Popper, science should attempt to disprove a theory, rather than attempt to continually support theoretical hypotheses.
How to reference this article: How to reference this article: McLeod, S. Back to top. Please also check out my profiles of two other great philosophers of science, Thomas Kuhn and Paul Feyerabend. I began to discern the paradox lurking at the heart of Karl Popper's career when, prior to interviewing him in , I asked other philosophers about him. Everyone said this opponent of dogmatism was almost pathologically dogmatic.
To arrange an interview, I telephoned the London School of Economics, where Popper had taught since the late s. A secretary said he generally worked at his home in a London suburb. When I called, a woman with an imperious, German-accented voice answered. She gave me a list of a dozen or so books by Sir Karl that I should read before the meeting.
After numerous faxes and calls, she set a date. When I asked for directions from a nearby train station, Mrs. Mew assured me that all the cab drivers knew where Sir Karl lived. Sir Karl Popper? The famous philosopher? Never heard of him, the driver said. He knew the street on which Popper lived, however, and we found Popper's home, a two-story cottage surrounded by neatly trimmed lawn and shrubs, with little difficulty.
A tall, handsome woman with short dark hair, wearing black pants and shirt, answered the door. Mew was only slightly less forbidding in person than over the telephone.
As she led me into the house, she told me that Sir Karl was tired. He had endured many interviews and congratulations brought on by his 90th birthday last month, and he had been toiling over an acceptance speech for the Kyoto Prize, known as Japan's Nobel.
I should expect to speak to him for only an hour at the most. I was trying to lower my expectations when Popper made his entrance. He was stooped and surprisingly short.
I had assumed the author of such autocratic prose would be tall. Yet he was as kinetic as a bantamweight boxer. He brandished an article I had written for Scientific American about how quantum mechanics is raising questions about the objectivity of physics.
He kept jumping up from his chair to forage for books or articles that could buttress a point. Striving to dredge a name or date from his memory, he kneaded his temples and gritted his teeth as if in agony. Words poured from him so rapidly and with so much momentum that I began to lose hope that I could ask my prepared questions. Popper emphasized that he had known all the titans of twentieth-century science: Einstein, Schrodinger, Heisenberg. He was talking all the time, allowing practically only one or two words to you and then at once cutting in.
As Mrs. Mew turned to leave, Popper asked her to find one of his books. She disappeared and returned empty-handed. Mew somehow rolled her eyes without really rolling them and vanished. He paused a moment, and I seized the opportunity to ask a question. You should ask me your questions!
I have wrongly taken the lead. You can ask me all your questions first. I noted that in his writings he seemed to abhor the notion of absolute truths. But he rejected the positivist belief that we can ever know that a theory is true. Popper disagreed with the positivist view that science can be reduced to a formal, logical system or method. A scientific theory is an invention, an act of creation, based more upon a scientist's intuition than upon pre-existing empirical data. It makes you proud to be a human being.
For similar reasons, Popper opposed determinism, which he saw as antithetical to human creativity and freedom.
0コメント